![]() |
[email protected] |
![]() |
3275638434 |
![]() |
![]() |
Paper Publishing WeChat |
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License
Descartes’ General Epistemology: A Contemporary Assessment
Tom Vinci
Full-Text PDF
XML 1058 Views
DOI:10.17265/2159-5313/2020.07.002
Dalhousie University, Halifax, Nova Scotia, Canada
There is a broad distinction in Descartes’ writings between doctrine and method. The staying power of these two elements has been unequal. Descartes’ doctrinal influence on contemporary epistemology has been largely as a foil against which some of its major currents have been developed. The situation is brighter on the methodological side. Here Descartes’ practice of beginning with common sense and moving, step by step, to philosophical conclusions is a practice much admired by contemporary philosophers. Still, the negative verdict on doctrine stands as the main verdict overall. I maintain that this verdict is undeserved.
I first distinguish between Descartes’ general epistemology and the purpose to which he puts it—the quest for certainty. I then argue for a positive verdict for his general epistemology. I do so by showing that Descartes has a non-normative account ofknowledgebut an “ethics of belief” in which the knowing comes first. Descartes thus anticipates what Sylvan calls the “knowledge-first” approach in general epistemology, which I defend. Relying on Audi’s distinction between “sources” and “reasons,” I show that Descartes’ analysis of knowledge proper, which I also defend, anticipates and improves the “factive access” analysis of knowledge due to McDowell.
general epistemology, analysis of knowledge, normativity, reasons, Descartes
Vinci, T. (2020). Descartes’ general epistemology: A contemporary assessment. Philosophy Study, 10(7), 414-423.
Audi, R. (2011). Epistemology (3rd ed.). New York: Routledge.
Adam, C., & Tannery, P. (Eds.). (1964). Oeuvres de Descartes (rev. ed.). Paris: Vrin/C.N.R.S.
Ayer, A. J. (1956). The problem of knowledge. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Bonjour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge Mass: Harvard University Press.
Cottinghmam, J., Stoothoff, R., & Murdoch, D. (Trans.). (1984). The philosophical writings of Descartes (Vol. II). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Crumley II, J. S. (Ed.). (1999). Readings in epistemology. Mountain View: Mayfield Press.
Gettier, E. (1963). Is knowledge true, justified belief. Analysis, 23, 121-123.
Ginsborg, H. (2018). Empiricism and normative constraint. In J. Gersel, R. T. Jensen, M. S. Thaning, and S. Overgaard (Eds.), In the light of experience: New essays on perception and reasons (pp. 101-140). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goldman, A. (1967). A causal theory of knowing. The Journal of Philosophy, 12, 355-372.
Longino, H. (1994). The fate of knowledge in social theories of science. In I. F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing epistemology: The social dimensions of knowledge (pp. 135-157). Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield.
McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Naamen-Zauderer, N. (2010). Descartes’ deontological turn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stroud, B. (1984). The significance of philosophical skepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sylvan, K. (2018). Knowledge as a non-normative relation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 97(1), 190-222.
Vinci, T. (2016). Contemporary analytic philosophy and Bayesian subjectivism: Why both are incoherent. Philosophy Study, 6(10), 578-585.
Vinci, T. (2008). Descartes and contemporary epistemology. In G. Robertson, G. McOuat, and T. Vinci (Eds.), Descartes and the modern (Chapter 13, pp. 254-284). Newcastle-upon-Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Press.
Vinci, T. C. (1998). Cartesian truth. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.